Karl Marx
Karl Marx was a German philosopher and political activist, well known for his creation of communist theory and association with fellow radical Friedrich Engels.
Marx's Historical Materialism
Marx, like many of the socialist revolutionary thinkers of his time, believed in progressive history, a theory of historical analysis that involves an end goal for all human history and society. In Marx’s mind, this end goal would be a communist utopia, which was built on the retaking of and redistribution of the means of production by the working class, or proletariat. Essentially, a communist revolution would not only be the best course of action for a society in upheaval over class divisions, but also the only and final course of action for such a society. This is the theory of historical materialism; that the productive capacity of a society, and its economic conditions, are the source of historical shifts and general trends. As a result of this progression of history, all exercises of power become contextualized as extensions of an illegitimate hierarchy produced by capitalism. The capitalist’s dominion over the worker, for example, is based on their invalid ownership of the means of production, and thereby their dominance within a capitalist society. Ultimately, historical materialism dictated that the forces of production would generate larger class divisions and ultimately resolve in a society that had no exploitative relationships between capitalist and workers, as workers would seize the means of production in a socialist revolution.
The Base and the Superstructure
These divisions and changes in society would come from the fundamental building blocks of communities in Marxist theory: the base, and the superstructure. While previous philosophers such as Adam Smith discussed a generally benevolent or malevolent human nature, Marxist human nature and morality are structured around these building blocks; as the economic base changes, so do the values and aspirations of human beings within that base. The priorities of the people within that economic base, in turn, influence the political superstructure, which is the larger system through which policy is made in society. Therefore, as economics shift and people change with those economics, the superstructure is assembled around the economic base. When observing industrialization and the increased inequality of wealth between upper and lower classes in the 19th century, as well as the anti-elite rebellions such as the French Revolution, Marx and Engels came to the conclusion that the economic base had changed to generate inequality among people, and that the political superstructure would be revolutionized by the changing of the economic base as the worker retook the means of production from the capitalist. In the Communist Manifesto, Marx brings up the base of capitalism as the industrial production process, while the superstructure is the political right to private property. Because of the interconnected nature of the industrial process being fundamentally at odds with the individualistic system of private property, Marx and Engels reasoned that capitalism would ultimately self-destruct from its own contradictions.
Karl Marx, Marvin Harris, and Cultural Materialism
When reading Marx’s theories of historical materialism, it is easy to identify his theories as part of a larger trend of materialistic analysis of human societies. The prominent cultural anthropologist Marvin Harris wrote in the early aughts about the concept of ‘cultural materialism,’ in which all human society was structured around the physical needs of people, whether that be hunger, thirst, the need for shelter, or the need for production to feed those aforementioned basic needs. The general thesis of these ideas is that humans, no matter how complex the systems they devise are, will be ultimately driven by base instincts; in Harris’s case, hunger drives traditions as widespread and diverse as the Eucharist or the worship of cows in Hinduism, while Marx’s theory of historical materialism firmly places every society and economic system into a mold of a shifting economic base and superstructure that will both ultimately aim towards a communist system, as production increases and private property is first established and then abolished. However, both Marx and Harris’s approaches betray a utility-minded focus toward history that concerningly does away with human concepts of meaningfulness that very much influence day-to-day decision-making. When one considers everything in terms of profit and production, then every ritual makes sense under those simplistic considerations; this was the exact criticism leveled at Harris by Marshall Sahlins, the pre-eminent cultural anthropologist and contemporary opponent of cultural materialism. In a response to Harris’s book, Sahlins uses the example of Aztec sacrifice to identify that the religion’s ritual practices far outweighed the potential bodily gain that Harris justified it with. Marx’s theory of history, unfortunately, is much the same in its logical extremism. Marx casts the entire shadow of history as aiming toward the changing of the superstructure to a world without exploitation, but he ignores the backsliding, improvements, and changes in the superstructure that have few to no sources in the economic base itself. The scale of the superstructure works on the level of the state, but local communities often make decisions based on group identity and ideology that often have little to do with the economic base. Even under Marxist morality theory, in which the economic base is the center of people’s values in society, practices such as religion are difficult to explain in a non-productive capacity. While it might make sense to give workers a Sabbath to ensure their future productivity and obedience, it makes little sense to give them dietary restrictions that would make them less likely to be well-fed and strong; despite this, many of the world’s major religions such as Hinduism or Buddhism spread a vegetarian diet. In this sense, historical materialism commits the central flaw of generalizing all of history into a theoretical framework that might not match reality in individual communities, even if it does on larger scales.